In "Looking into the Black Box," (New York Times, 11/24/13) Michael
Strevens raises an interesting question.
Do we understand something if we know its causes? He gives
an example:
To understand the
northern lights, for example, is to understand how charged particles in the
solar wind are guided to the earth’s magnetic poles, where colliding
energetically with oxygen and nitrogen molecules they cause ionization that
results in the emission of light. The guiding, the colliding, the ionizing, the
emission are all causal processes; to see how these processes unfold is to
understand the aurora.
Is this really true? I don’t think so. For one thing, I don’t
think we really understand light at
all? We’ve been able to devise increasingly elaborate descriptions of it, using
terms from the realm of physics that we don’t really understand either. This type
of analysis has its uses. But isn’t it annoying to stand on a deathly quiet, snow-covered
lake next to an icy know-it-all who informs us that “those ghostly bands of
green and white above our heads are merely an emission of light caused by
collisions of ionized particles in the solar wind”? Something is missing
here.
Without quite answering the initial question, Strevens brings
up a second one that’s no less interesting: is causality itself a valid
principle or merely a useful way of codifying relations between things so we
can predict their behavior? These reflections lead him to an implicit admission
that “understanding,” whatever it may be, must take us beyond the realm of
causal links. Yet he never abandons the idea that to understand something is to
break it into parts and figure out how it works.
It might be more illuminating, I think, to leave the
Northern Lights aside for a bit and examine something with which we have
greater intuitive affinity. How about Bach’s Art of Fugue, which I’m listening to right now.
Bach was a master of counterpoint, and a popular exercise
among composition teachers is to require that their students analyze a section
of this magisterial work, pinpointing how the themes and inversions, the canons
and stretta passages, fit together. In doing so, the students are supposed to
come to a better understanding of counterpoint, and also of what
remarkable things can be created following a fairly strict set of rules and a
small collection of motifs. And I suspect they often do.
Once again, we’re examining how the parts of a thing work.
But do we thereby arrive at a better understanding of The Art of Fugue itself? Once again, I think not.
We understand The Art
of Fugue not by taking the pieces apart, but by putting them together—inside
our heads. It’s an act, not of analysis, but of synthesis. And also of appreciation.
I have sat through more than a few pre-concert lectures during
which I’ve been told that if I would only cast aside my hidebound prejudices
and remained non-judgmental, if I patiently studied the score in an attempt to
grasp the clever things an Elliot Carter, say, was doing in the third movement
of his quartet, I’d come to recognize its worth. This isn’t true. I might develop
a heightened appreciation for Carter’s cleverness…but the worth of music lies
entirely in its sounds. If the sounds don’t come together in a pleasing
way, intuitively, inside our heads, the
music is worthless—at least to us.
No doubt there are plenty of compositions that I lack the
sensitivity to appreciate. And there are ways of sounding “pleasing” that will
appeal to us only rarely, depending on the mood. The other day I was listening
to György Kurtág’s Kafka-Fragmente, and enjoying it. Soprano and violin fighting it
out. In the liner notes I read:
Sudden, broken, the
fragment is completed not only by its companions sounding around it but by us
in silence. We see ourselves, too, in these shivers of mirror, in their sharp
but uncertain edges; between humor and anxiety, between withdrawal and
explosion, between assertion and indecision.
It’s a lovely partnership, though I wouldn’t want to go
there again anytime soon. The author of the commentary, in comparing the piece to
various emotions, probably leads us closer to understanding it that any technical
analysis could.
There is no need to downplay the importance of analysis, of
“tasking things apart,” in our quest for understanding. But in the end it means
little if we can’t also put things together and feel them at work inside us. Such
a feat come naturally to some, though it requires not only analysis and
intuition, but also judgment. And if this in true in the realm of art, where
the artifacts in question have been created
intentionally, it’s even more so in the realm of history more broadly
conceived, where many events take place as a result of fortuitous interactions.
The New York Times released its annual list of the ten best books of the year yesterday.
I found several of the descriptions interesting in themselves. For example,
here is how the editors described The Sleepwalkers: How Europe Went to War in 1914 by
Christopher Clark:
And here is how they describe After the Music
Stopped: The Financial
Crisis, the Response, and the Work Ahead by Alan S. Blinder.
Blinder’s terrific
book on the financial meltdown of 2008 argues that it happened because of a
“perfect storm,” in which many unfortunate events occurred simultaneously,
producing a far worse outcome than would have resulted from just a single
cause. Blinder criticizes both the Bush and Obama administrations, especially
for letting Lehman Brothers fail, but he also praises them for taking steps to
save the country from falling into a serious depression. Their response to the
near disaster, Blinder says, was far better than the public realizes.
Here we see scholars at work, taking things apart but also
exercising their judgment; looking for causes, but only sometimes finding them.
Readers like me can usually do no better than to single out a few pithy
one-liners to remember, but these scholars, who understand their chosen subjects far better than we do, would
probably agree that the greater truth lies in the music of the narrative
itself.
You may object that there is nothing very scientific about my
description of understanding. But the association of “science” with “understanding”
is merely one of the odd prejudices of our time. Recent studies have underscored
the fact that scientific research is far more likely to produce spurious
results than accurate ones. (See Economist, Oct. 19, p. 26-30 for an overview).
The type of understanding
I’m describing here also has a long history, though it’s now largely forgotten.
For example, in 1821 William von Humboldt gave a lecture to the Prussian
Academy of Science, “On the Historian’s Task,” which became a
landmark in the field. Here von Humboldt asserts that “an event…is only
partially visible in the world of the senses; the rest has to be added by
intuition, inference, and guesswork.” He compares the historian to the poet,
then draws an important distinction between them: “The crucial difference,
which removes all potential dangers, lies in the fact that the historian
subordinates his imagination to experience and the investigation of reality…the
imagination does not act as pure fancy and is, therefore, more properly called the intuitive faculty or connective ability.”
If you read on in the essay, you’ll come upon expressions
such as “inner necessity” and “the breath of life in the whole and the inner character which speaks through it…”
It would almost seem that the historian is being called upon to fashion a work
of art from events, in the same way that Bach fashioned The Art of Fugue from a few select motifs.
Von Humboldt would
probably agree. At one point he writes: “Hence, the historian, in order to
perform the task of his profession, has to compose the narrative of events in
such a way that the reader’s emotions will be stirred by it as if by reality
itself.”
A good deal more could be said on this subject, but I’d like
to add just one more piece of the story. I’d like to take us back yet another
century to 1711, the publication date of Shaftesbury’s Characteristics. In this collection of essays (specifically the essay
titled “An Inquiry Concerning Virtue,
or Merit”) Lord Shaftesbury introduces the notion of moral sense, a
faculty he compares to aesthetic sense. The basic point is that there is no way
for us to develop a sense of right and
wrong via logic or reasoning, if we don’t already possess a fundamental
humaneness or benevolence or sense of justice.
This may seem obvious, but there are many who would challenge
the theory, and even call it “dangerous.” On the other hand, the historian Ernst
Cassirer has described Shaftesbury’s theory, and its overarching significance,
in the following terms:
[Shaftesbury] founds a philosophy
in which aesthetics not only represents a systematic province but occupies the
central position of the whole intellectual structure. According to Shaftesbury,
the question of the nature of truth is inseparable from that of the nature of
beauty, for the two questions agree both in their grounds and in their ultimate
principle. All beauty is truth, just as all truth can be understood basically
only through the meaning of form, that is, the meaning of beauty. That
everything real partakes of form, that it is no chaotic amorphous mass, but
possesses rather an inner proportion and evidences in its nature a certain
structure, and in its development and motion a rhythmic order and rule: this
is the fundamental phenomenon in which the purely intellectual, the supersensible origin of the real manifests itself.
There
are echoes of Plato in Shaftesbury’s emphasis on form, and anticipations of Hegel
in his rarefied idea of “the real,” but we don’t have time to explore those
connections now. We can only note that Shaftesbury is wrong to equate form with beauty outright;
the suggestion that everything in history is beautiful is simply outrageous.
But in the same way that an artist brings form to his or her materials, making
them beautiful, the historian uncovers the form of events, which is their truth.
It isn’t the aesthetic faculty at work in this case, however, but the moral faculty.
And when the historian stirs a reader’s
emotions (to return to von Humboldt’s remark above), it’s the moral sense
that’s being engaged and uplifted.
Where
does causality fit into all of this? Nowhere, as far as I can see. A fan of The Art of Fugue might suggest that every
note is perfect and necessary—nothing is gratuitous or out of place. Yet few
would suggest, I think, that one note or phrase “caused” the next, because Bach’s
creative genius is present in every line.
The same can be said about history.
There is little point in considering “what ifs” except as an imaginative—that is
to say, a poetic—exercise. But poetry isn’t history. History is the study of
what actually happened. And the radical force careening through history, defying
merely causal forces at every turn of the path, is the creative spirit of the individual
agents involved in it. Where such a force is not involved, there is nothing “real”
to be found. We might as well be admiring charged particles in the solar wind colliding
with oxygen and nitrogen molecules in the upper atmosphere.
It’s
a nice show, but it doesn’t engage our moral sense, and therefore, there isn’t
much truth to be found in it.
1 comment:
Yes, this is very much attractive and beautiful. Alaska and Norway these are really the best and very popular places to see northern lights. Book Trip to see the northern lights
Post a Comment